Get all the latest news, tips, and commentaries - sign up for our free newsletter.
tacit knowledge - Knowledge that enters into the production of behaviors and/or the constitution of mental states but is not ordinarily accessible to consciousness. See also cognize, knowledge, implicit memory, Background, rules.
[Introduction][Varieties of TK][TK and Explicit Belief][References]
Although the expression "tacit knowledge" appears to have been introduced by Michael Polanyi (1958/1974), the idea that certain cognitive processes and/or behaviors are undergirded by operations inaccessible to consciousness -- by a cognitive unconscious, as Reber (1995) calls it -- goes back at least as far as Helmholtz's work in the 19th century (Reber 1995, p. 15). A more recent and influential formulation of this basic idea can be found in Lashley (1956).
The distinction between tacit knowledge and explicit knowledge has sometimes been expressed in terms of knowing-how and knowing-that, respectively (Ryle 1949/1984, pp. 25-61), or in terms of a corresponding distinction between embodied knowledge and theoretical knowledge. On this account knowing-how or embodied knowledge is characteristic of the expert, who acts, makes judgments, and so forth without explicitly reflecting on the principles or rules involved. The expert works without having a theory of his or her work; he or she just performs skillfully without deliberation or focused attention. Knowing-that, by contrast, involves consciously accessible knowledge that can be articulated and is characteristic of the person learning a skill through explicit instruction, recitation of rules, attention to his or her movements, etc. While such declarative knowledge may be needed for the acquisition of skills, the argument goes, it no longer becomes necessary for the practice of those skills once the novice becomes an expert in exercising them, and indeed it does seem to be the case that, as Polanyi argued, when we acquire a skill, we acquire a corresponding understanding that defies articulation (Polanyi 1958/1974).
But the distinction between knowing-how and knowing-that breaks down upon examination. As Dretske has pointed out (Dretske 1988, p. 116), knowing-how involves more than just a certain technical or physical "know-how"; it also involves knowing how to obtain desired end-states, knowing what to do in order to obtain them, and knowing when to do it. Implied in all this is that knowing how to perform action _A_ means knowing that certain things are the case regarding, for example, tools, the situation in which _A_-ing takes place, and so forth. If, as seems likely, this is the case, then knowing-how would seem to be closely bound up with, if not dependent on, some variety of knowing-that. Even if we are able to isolate the know-how that goes into _A_-ing, it isn't clear that the processes, involved -- which narrowly understood may amount to little more than automatized physical sequences or muscular reflexes -- count as cognitive in any interesting way.
Note, though, that in rejecting the distinction between knowing-how and knowing-that we are not thereby denying the existence of tacit knowledge per se; rather, we are denying its exclusive identification with procedural operations that may in the end have little to do with knowledge as such. What is rejected is not the idea that skillful (or other) activities may rely on content states that are inaccessible to consciousness (or that conscious attention is not necessary for the exercise of a given skill), but rather the notion that a given behavior or performance stands as the proper criterion for possession of the tacit knowledge in question. Certainly there is no reason to suppose that the knowing-that which would seem to come into play even in expert performance cannot be tacit.
That an exhaustive equation of tacit knowledge with pretheoretical, skilled expertise cannot be maintained becomes particularly clear when we consider that one widely accepted paradigm of tacit knowledge is to be found in language competence (e.g., Chomsky 1986, pp. 263-273; 1980, pp. 69-70; 1972, pp. 103-104). In contrast to the variety of tacit knowledge described above, knowledge of language is not understood to constitute a skill, and thus to consist in a capacity to do something -- and consequently to have possession predicated on the appropriate behavioral criteria -- but rather is a properly cognitive capacity, and therefore defined in terms of mental states and structures that are not always or reliably manifested in behaviors or performances (Chomsky 1986, pp. 9-10; 1980, p. 48).
We might point to a third kind of tacit knowledge, which consists in what might be thought of as the presuppositions or stances many of our actions and behaviors commit us to. Such stances are not occurrent beliefs, although they may be expressed as occurrent beliefs under the appropriate circumstances. Rather, they constitute a kind of cognitive background or disposition to believe that certain things are the case (cf Searle 1995, 1992, 1983; see also entry on The Background). An example of this kind of tacit knowledge is that objects are rigid, a bit of knowledge few people ever bother to formulate, but which is evidenced in such basic everyday actions as sitting in a chair. Because such knowledge is expressible as a propositional content, it would seem to be a case of tacit knowing-that. (It is tacit knowledge of this sort that may ultimately explain the cognitive dimension at work in those cases held up as examples of embodied knowledge or knowing-how.) These tacit stances or presuppositions are perhaps best described as tacit beliefs or hypotheses that can be falsified under the appropriate conditions.
While the kinds of tacit knowledge underlying skills or expert performances on the one hand, and cognitive competences like knowledge of language on the other, appear to be domain-specific, this third type of tacit knowledge would appear to be more generally applicable. It seems to be the case that the cognitive content associated with tacit beliefs of this sort comes into play across a diverse set of activities and domains. Much, though by no means all, of the heterogeneous set of biological and cultural stances and capacities that Searle refers to as The Background (see entry on The Background) may be thought of as consisting in a generally applicable tacit knowledge of this sort.
Although the three conceptions of tacit knowledge outlined above differ from each other in significant ways, they do have one central feature in common, and that is the postulation of content states that are at once causally efficacious and inaccessible to (or not ordinarily accessed by) consciousness.
Tacit Knowledge and Explicit Belief
As with ascriptions of rule-following, the ascription of tacit knowledge states to people is a theoretical move meant to explain behavior or cognitive operations (see entry on rules). What makes ascriptions of tacit knowledge distinctive is the asymmetry between the richness of the ascribed content state and the relative poverty of the subjective experience corresponding to that state. Simply put, the person to whom we ascribe tacit knowledge has little or no conscious experience of what it is we claim is causing his or her activity. But although the relation between the cognitive unconscious on the one hand and conscious states on the other is complex, we might offer the following observations.
First, at least some forms of tacit knowledge would appear to differ very little from ordinary knowledge outside of their being tacit. This would seem to be true of much of the tacit knowledge assigned to the third category above, and possibly true as well of knowledge of language.
In regard to the latter, Chomsky has held that knowledge of grammar involves propositional knowledge and belief (1986, p. 265; 1980, p. 93), as does ordinary knowledge. In addition, he observes that a speaker's tacit knowledge of grammar is inferentially available to interact with his or her other systems of knowledge and belief (1980, p. 92), as speakers' decisions to use their tacit knowledge are influenced by their "goals, beliefs, expectations, and so forth" (1986, p. 261).
In regard to the former, i.e., the third variety of tacit knowledge described above, it seems essential that such general content as appears to be involved should be available for integration into a person's beliefs and other attitude states. Far from existing behind a kind of firewall separating it from ordinary beliefs and other attitude states, at least some forms of tacit knowledge would seem to have to be a part of a person's overall network of attitude states, and to exert influence on -- as well as to be influenced by -- those states.
Second, it may be the case that many ordinary beliefs themselves are largely dispositional or tacit. Our having consciously thought about or avowed a belief may be a purely contingent fact about us rather than a necessary feature of beliefs. When a belief of ours is brought to our attention, we do, under ordinary circumstances, tend to recognize it as such. The dispositional aspect thus consists in this: when confronted with a statement or other formulation of what appears to be a person's tacit knowledge that _p_, that person ordinarily will be disposed to feel/hold/agree that _p_.
There is thus reason to suppose that at least some -- though by no means all -- forms of tacit knowledge can behave like ordinary dispositions to believe, and accordingly can be brought to awareness given the proper circumstances. We might say then that these kinds of tacit knowledge are tacit to the extent that they are initially inaccessible to the person to whom they are attributed, but that given the proper conditions, this inaccessibility can be converted to the kind of accessibility enjoyed by our ordinary knowledge.
Chomsky, N. (1972). Language and Mind. San Diego, Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. [bookstore]
Chomsky, N. (1980). Rules and Representations. New York, Columbia University Press. [bookstore]
Chomsky, N. (1986). Knowledge of Language. New York, Praeger. [bookstore]
Dretske, F. (1991). Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes. Cambridge MA, MIT Press. [bookstore]
Lashley, K. (1956). "Cerebral Organization and Behavior." In Solomon, H., et al. eds., The Brain and Human Behavior, pp. 1-18. Baltimore, Williams and Wilkins. [bookstore]
Polanyi, M. (1958/1974). Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post- Critical Philosophy. Chicago, University of Chicago Press.
Reber, A. (1995). Implicit Learning and Tacit Knowledge: An Essay on the Cognitive Unconscious. New York, Oxford University Press.
Ryle, G. (1949/1984). The Concept of Mind. Chicago, University of Chicago Press. [bookstore]
Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. New York, Cambridge University Press. [bookstore]
Searle, J. (1992). The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. [bookstore]
Searle, J. (1995). The Construction of Social Reality. New York, Free Press. [bookstore]